Institutio Oratoria

Quintilian

Quintilian. Institutio Oratoria, Volume 1-4. Butler, Harold Edgeworth, translator. Cambridge, Mass; London: Harvard University Press, William Heinemann Ltd., 1920-1922.

But for the fact that Cicero [*](Top. iii. 12. ) has done so, I should regard it as absurd to add to these what is styled the conjugate argument, such as

Those who perform a just act, act justly,
a self-evident fact requiring no proof; or again,
Every man has a common right to send his cattle to graze in a common pasture.

Some call these arguments derived from causes or efficients by the Greek name ἐκβάσεις that is, results; for in such cases the only point considered is how one thing results from another. Those arguments which prove the lesser from the greater or the greater from the less or equals from equals are styled apposite or comparative.

A conjecture as to a fact is confirmed by argument from something greater in the following sentence:

If a man commit sacrilege, he will also commit theft
; from something less, in a sentence such as
He who lies easily and openly will commit perjury
; from something equal in a sentence such as
He who has taken a bribe to give a false verdict will take a bribe to give false witness.

Points of law may be proved in a similar manner; from something greater, as in the sentence

If it is lawful to kill an adulterer, it is lawful to scourge him
; from something less,
If it is lawful to kill a man attempting theft by night, how much more lawful is it to kill one who attempts robbery with violence
; from something equal,
The penalty which is just in the case of parricide is also just in the case of matricide.
In all these cases we follow the syllogistic method. [*](See III. vi. 15, 43, 88.)

The following type of argument on the other hand is more serviceable in questions turning

v4-6 p.251
on definition or quality. [*]( See iii. 6. passim. )
If strength is good for the body, health is no less good.
If theft is a crime, sacrilege is a greater crime.
If abstinence is a virtue, so is self-control.
If the world is governed by providence, the state also requires a government.
If a house cannot be built without a plan, what of a whole city?
If naval stores require careful supervision, so also do arms.

I am content to treat this type of argument as a genus without going further; others however divide it into species. For we may argue from several things to one or from one thing to several; hence arguments such as

What has happened once may happen often.
We may also argue from a part to a whole, from genus to species, from that which contains to that which is contained, from the difficult to the easy, from the remote to the near, and similarly from the opposites of all these to their opposites.

Now all these arguments deal with the greater or the less or else with things that are equal, and if we follow up such fine distinctions, there will be no limit to our division into species. For the comparison of things is infinite; things may be more pleasant, more serious, more necessary, more honourable, more useful. I say no more for fear of falling into that very garrulity which I deprecate.

The number of examples of these arguments which I might quote is likewise infinite, but I will only deal with a very few. As an example of argument from something greater take the following example from the pro Caecina [*](XV. 43.)

Shall we suppose that that which alarms whole armies caused no alarm to a peaceful company of lawyers?
As an instance of argument from something easier, take this passage
v4-6 p.253
from the speech against Clodius and Curio: [*]( A lost speech of Cicero to which reference is made in III. vii. 2. )
Consider whether it would have been easy for you to secure the praetorship, when he in whose favour you withdrew failed to secure election?

The following [*]( xvi. 45. Caecina had attempted to take possession of lands left him by will, but was driven off by armed force. Cicero has just pointed out that there were precedents for regarding the mere sight of armed men in occupation of the property claimed as sufficient proof of violence. ) provides an example of argument from something more difficult:

I beg you, Tubero, to remark that I, who do not hesitate to speak of my own deed, venture to speak of that performed by Ligarius
; and again,
Has not Ligarius reason for hope, when I am permitted to intercede with you for another?
For an argument drawn from something less take this passage from the pro Caecinaa [*](pro Lig. iii. 8 and x. 31. Cicero's point is that he has been a much more bitter opponent of Caesar than Ligarius, and yet he has been pardoned while Ligarius has not. ) :
Really! Is the knowledge that the men were armed sufficient to prove that violence was offered, and the fact that he fell into their hands insufficient?
Well, then, to give a brief summary of the whole question, arguments are drawn from persons, causes, place and time (which latter we have divided into preceding, contemporary and subsequent), from resources (under which we include instruments), from manner (that is, how a thing has been done), from definition, genus, species, difference, property, elimination, division, beginnings, increase, consummation, likes, unlikes, contradictions, consequents, efficients, effects, results, and comparison, which is subdivided into several species.

I think I should also add that arguments are drawn not merely from admitted facts, but from fictitious suppositions, which the Greeks style καθ᾽ ὑπόθεσιν and that this latter type of argument falls into all the same divisions as those which I have

v4-6 p.255
mentioned above, since there may be as many species of fictitious arguments as there are of true arguments.

When I speak of fictitious arguments I mean the proposition of something which, if true, would either solve a problem or contribute to its solution, and secondly the demonstration of the similarity of our hypothesis to the case under consideration. To make this the more readily intelligible to youths who have not yet left school, I will first of all illustrate it by examples of a kind familiar to the young.

There is a law to the effect that

the man who refuses to support his parents is liable to imprisonment.
A certain man fails to support his parents and none the less objects to going to prison. He advances the hypothesis that he would be exempt from such a penalty if he were a soldier, an infant. or if he were absent from home on the service of the state. Again in the case where a hero is allowed to choose his reward [*](cp. VII. v. 4. ) we might introduce the hypotheses of his desiring to make himself a tyrant or to overthrow the temples of the gods.

Such arguments are specially useful when we are arguing against the letter of the law, and are thus employed by Cicero in the pro Caecina [*]( xix. 55. Quintilian merely quotes fragments of Cicero's arguments. The sense of the passages omitted is supplied in brackets. The interdict of the praetor had ordered Caecina's restoration. His adversary is represented by Cicero as attempting to evade compliance by verbal quibbles. ) :

[The interdict contains the words,] ' whence you or your household or your agent had driven him.' If your steward alone had driven me out, [it would not, I suppose, be your household but a member of your household that had driven me out]. . . . If indeed you owned no slave except the one who drove me out, [you would cry, 'If I possess a household at all, I admit that my household drove you out'].
Many other examples might be quoted from the same work.

But fictitious suppositions are also exceedingly useful when we are concerned with the quality of an act [*](pro Mur —. xxxix. 83. Cicero argues that Murena's election as consul is necessary to save the state from Catiline. If the jury now condemn him, they will be doing exactly what Catiline and his accomplices, now in arms in Etruria, would do if they could try him. ) :

If
v4-6 p.257
Catiline could try this case assisted by a jury composed of those scoundrels whom he led out with him he would condemn Lucius Murena.
It is useful also for amplification [*](Phil. II. xxv. 63. This = vomiting. Cicero contimes who would not have thought it disgraceful. ) :
If this had happened to you during dinner in the midst of your deep potations
; or again, [*]( Probably an allusion to Cat. i. 7, where Cicero makes the state reproach Catiline for his conduct. )
If the state could speak.

Such in the main are the usual topics of proof as specified by teachers of rhetoric, but it is not sufficient to classify them generically in our instructions, since from each of them there arises an infinite number of arguments, while it is in the very nature of things impossible to deal with all their individual species. Those who have attempted to perform this latter task have exposed themselves in equal degree to two disadvantages, saying too much and yet failing to cover the whole ground.

Consequently the majority of students, finding themselves lost in an inextricable maze, have abandoned all individual effort, including even that which their own wits might have placed within their power, as though they were fettered by certain rigid laws, and keeping their eyes fixed upon their master have ceased to follow the guidance of nature.

But as it is not in itself sufficient to know that all proofs are drawn either from persons or things, because each of these groups is subdivided into a number of different heads so he who has learned that arguments must be drawn from antecedent, contemporary or subsequent facts will not be sufficiently instructed in the knowledge of the method of handling arguments to understand what arguments are to be drawn from the circumstances of each particular case;

especially as the majority of proofs are to be found in the special circumstances of individual cases and have

v4-6 p.259
no connexion with any other dispute, and therefore while they are the strongest, are also the least obvious, since, whereas we derive what is common to all cases from general rules, we have to discover for ourselves whatever is peculiar to the case which we have in hand.

This type of argument may reasonably be described as drawn from circumstances, there being no other word to express the Greek περίστασις or from those things which are peculiar to any given case. For instance, in the case of the priest who having committed adultery desired to save his own life by means of the law [*]( This law and those which follow are imaginary laws invented for the purposes of the schools of rhetoric. ) which gave him the power of saving one life, the appropriate argument to employ against him would run as follows:

You would save more than one guilty person, since, if you were discharged, it would not be lawful to put the adulteress to death.
For such an argument follows from the law forbidding the execution of the adulteress apart from the adulterer.

Again, take the case falling under the law which lays down that bankers may pay only half of what they owe, while permitted to recover the whole of what they are owed. One banker requires payment of the whole sum owed him by another banker. The appropriate argument supplied by the subject to the creditor is that there was special reason for the insertion of the clause [*]( The argument is far from clear. The case assumes that by a species of moratorium a banker may be released from payment of his debts in full to ordinary creditors. This moratorium does not however apparently apply to debts contracted between banker and banker. ) sanctioning the recovery of the whole of a debt by a banker, since there was no need of such a law as against others, inasmuch as all have the right to recover the whole of a debt from any save a banker.